Saturday, December 26, 2015

The Mystery of Divine Foreknowledge

Abstract

     This is a review or 'precis' of the book "Divine Foreknowledge: Four Views," By James Beilby and Paul Eddy, Eds.  This post addresses from the book four different perspectives on how God could know all things but yet allow free will and avoid being the Author of sin.

Introduction

     Does God know all things?  The Open Theism view answers the question negatively, arguing God does not exhaustively settle or know all things future.[3]  Does God in His foreknowledge and sovereignty preserve man's free agency?  The Augustinian-Calvinist view holds God decrees all things, leaving free will to be understood through the lens of compatiblism.[4]  Does God have freedom to act providentially logically consequent to His divine decree?  Advocates of the Simple Foreknowledge view are not sure.[5]  Presuming man has free agency, does God know how free agents would behave in all possible circumstances?  The Middle Knowledge view proposes a mechanism to answer this question in the affirmative.[6]  The debate within contemporary evangelicalism concerning divine foreknowledge engages significant theological doctrines including the nature and mode of God's foreknowledge, the operative mode of God's sovereignty, and whether mankind really has libertarian freedom or not.[7]   

Open Theism View

     While God is sovereign over history, the "Openness" view argues that Scriptural exegesis does not warrant the conclusion that future events are "exhaustively" settled by God, or even foreknown by Him![8] "Reality, in other words, is composed of both settled and open aspects."[9]  While God declares through the prophet Isaiah that he "...declares the end from the beginning, and from long ago what is not yet done...,"[10] Boyd contends God settles some future events without settling all future being events.

Open Theism View Supporting Arguments

     Our own decision-making process reveals we presuppose it is within our power to choose between different "possible futures."[11]  Even physical reality exhibits a combination of deterministic and quantum indeterministic properties demonstrating the possibility all future events may not be settled.[12]  

     Language describing God exhaustively knowing the future in Scripture are taken literally, yet passages referring to God regretting, or changing His Mind, or pronouncing conditional curses or blessings, are classically interpreted as figurative.  Boyd argues since the language is the same in both motifs, the different interpretive approaches used is not justified.[13]  In passages where God expresses surprise, regret, or frustration,[14] Boyd argues interpreting these figuratively renders them meaningless.[15]  For example if II Peter 3:9 is analogized, this passage requires us to conclude God did not mean He wishes no one would perish, and He has preordained people for hell.[16]  "If it is difficult for the classical view to explain why God strives with people He is certain will not be saved, it is even more difficult to explain why God would create these people in the first place."[17] 

     Several passages suggest conditional terms in God's dealings with man[18], where future counterfactuals were possible.  In Exodus 13:17, "God actually reveals His inner thoughts and motives ─ things we would never know if He didn't tell us.  And we find to some extent God thinks about the future in terms of possibilities."[19]  Boyd reasons that God uses passages like this to teach that He can and does change His mind, and if those passages were interpreted figuratively, they would be logically incoherent.[20]

Responses to Open Theism View

     Hunt suggests Boyd equivocates the term "settled" with "determined" regarding future events, and confuses God's omnipotent power to make something happen with knowing it will come to pass."[21]  Hunt agrees God may have left some things causally open to happen, but He knows all things that will happen.[22]  Hunt negates the Open Theism response to the problem of evil with this query "The idea that God becomes aware of contingent events only as they happen, just like we do, is supposed to make God's failure to prevent horrendous evils somehow more comprehensible.  But how?"[23]

     Craig states if God knows certain counterfactuals, they must be true.[24]  Yet, "...since Boyd affirms divine omniscience and yet denies that God knows future contingencies, he must hold that such propositions are not true.  If such propositions are true, the Boyd's view undermines divine omniscience."[25]  Craig argues Open Theism denies that God has complete knowledge of the future yet affirms He is omniscient, which fails the logical principle of Bivalence.[26]

     Helm contends the Open Theism view of scriptural interpretation is flawed,[27]  presupposing that God is mutable; it allows a false philosophical construct to be employed in the interpretation of Scripture.[28]  Open Theism posits God's grace is causally necessary but not sufficient to save without man's free will acceptance, which Helm contends damages God's omnipotence as His will could then be frustrated by sinful man.[29]

Simple Foreknowledge View

     It is God's very nature to be all knowing, concerning all truth in the past, present and future, knowing all truths and believing no falsities, and containing no gaps to be filled in by future events.[30]  Hunt asserts Simple Divine Foreknowledge (F) is sufficient to refute objections without explanation as to how God knows the future.[31]  Hunt argues "...any alternative to Simple Foreknowledge must be justified on the grounds other than its ability to escape the Problem of Human Freedom, the Problem of Divine Agency and the Problem of Divine Providence."[32]

Simple Foreknowledge View Supporting Arguments

     Hunt avers that while (F) is not precisely defined in Scripture, dozens of examples show that God's knowledge is perfect; having a complete apprehension of the future and what is presently happening, including people's thoughts.[33]  God is attributed supreme divine perfection, and necessarily must have superlative knowledge, lacking in knowing anything that is true for God achieve what He wills.[34]

Resolving the Problem of Human Freedom

     Given God's infallible foreknowledge of a future event, Hunt asserts this necessitates the event will happen, but that antecedent knowledge of a future choice -- the "accidental necessity" of that event -- does not violate free will.[35]  Hunt rejects the Boethian view that God is atemporal and sees everything "presently," because it denies (F).[36]  Hunt also argues that where the Calvinist view asserts that, apart from God, man will always freely choose according to his sin nature, this denies free agency because any choice that is made is causally contingent on God.[37]  

     Hunt dismisses the Ockhamist argument, showing that "soft facts" essentially assert that God is not omniscient if it were possible for Him to believe something that was not real or potentially untrue.[38]  Hunt agrees with the Augustinian-Calvinist view that even when a free agent's choices are restricted to what God foreknows, they remain morally accountable.[39]  Hunt avers that God does not cause something "necessarily" by knowing it, as in the case of Adam's sin, "God's believing that Adam will sin depends on Adam's future sinning and not the other way around."[40]

Resolving the Problem of Divine Agency

     The objection raised is that by knowing the future already, God is "limited" to act only on what He knows of the future.[41]  Hunt uses an analogy of watching a video of your future that necessarily compels you to live out the future you have seen.  He dismisses the "intention-acquisition" dilemma by noting that while God is an intentional agent, even with propositional knowledge of what "will come to pass," God retains the power to decide what to do practically, and that God's omniscience only determines the propositional belief, not God's free agency to act.[42]

Resolving the Problem of Divine Providence

     The problem presents God as unable to respond to prayer "contrary to fact" of events in the future He foreknows.[43]  Possessing information about the future contrary to fact does not limit free agency, as Hunt explains "...only its use can generate explanatory loops."[44]  He argues that God's inability to employ His foreknowledge providentially would not prove (F) false, but further doctrinal analysis is needed to resolve this given God's maximal excellence and omnipotence.[45]

Responses to the Simple Foreknowledge View

     Boyd contends Simple Foreknowledge limits providential control by committing all future events known by God to be "necessarily" fixed.[46]  Boyd rejects Hunt's use of the Frankfurt analogy to explain how Simple Foreknowledge can logically coexist with man's free agency.  The analogy ignores mental processes of the actors, and by overriding their decisions, destroys the actor's free agency.[47]

     Craig rebuts Hunt's analogy that purports to prove that fatalism is true and that every past event is now "necessary," rendering impossible any act that would make God's knowledge of that future event in the past now untrue.[48]  Craig argues this does not prove fatalism is true because God is aware of future contingent propositions, and as they transpire to an actualized truth, they no longer are held as future conditional propositions.[49]  This, Craig contends, does not "lock" the future deterministically based on past "future" knowledge of counterfactuals held by God.[50]  Craig continues that since Hunt contends a causal link exists between God's foreknowledge of an event and a person's ability to do "A" or fail to do "A," Simple Foreknowledge is not compatible with free agency.[51]

     By denying the PAP in defense of Simple Foreknowledge, Helm contends Hunt is committed to some form of determinism that is not identified by Hunt.[52]  As a result, the claim by Hunt that the Augustinian-Calvinist view is fatalistic would also apply to the Simple Foreknowledge view.[53]  From Hunt's original conclusion that PAP is incompatible with human freedom, Helm then argues that since causal determinism is also incompatible with PAP, causal determinism must then be compatible with human freedom.[54]  Helm challenges Hunt's charge that the Augustinian-Calvinist view is fatalistic, since Simple Foreknowledge also denies indeterministic free will, it would also be fatalistic.

Middle Knowledge View

     The Middle Knowledge view attempts to explain God's omniscience not in just the terms of what will happen and what could have happened, but also what would have happened (counterfactuals) in the future had other world circumstances been in effect.[55]  The Middle Knowledge view contends God has full and unhindered knowledge of all counterfactuals, which have the property of the antecedent or consequent clauses of a statement being contrary to fact.[56] 

Logical Properties of Middle Knowledge

     Logically prior to God's decree of creation, He had natural knowledge of all necessary truths, including all possible future events ─ or what possibly could be.[57]  Logically subsequent to God's creative decree, God has free knowledge of all potential contingent truths about creation ─ what will be, past, present, and future.[58]  Where then does God's knowledge logically exist of what would be?  

     Dominican theologians postulated God's knowledge of counterfactuals was logically subsequent to the creative decree, because prior to the creative decree, no counterfactuals were knowable.[59]  Jesuits including Luis de Molina maintained God's knowledge of counterfactuals was logically prior to the divine decree.  They argued the Dominican position would destroy free agency if the divine decree logically preceded God's knowledge of counterfactuals because God would have decreed all possible actions.[60]  Placing God's knowledge of counterfactuals logically prior to His divine decree allows free agency without hindering God in arranging circumstances to achieve His Will.[61]

Middle Knowledge View Supporting Arguments

Craig cites biblical examples such as the warning to Zedekiah if he does not surrender to the Babylonians.[62]  Isaiah, Amos, and Jonah were given prophecies that were counterfactuals to what actually happened.[63]  Jesus told Pilate "If my kingdom were of this world my followers would fight..."[64]  Since it is logically impossible for God to believe falsities, counterfactuals must be "potentially true" in some circumstance, which Craig cites as scriptural evidence of middle knowledge.

     Craig responds to fatalist reasoning stating Middle Knowledge corrects the logical fallacy that what God foreknows must 'necessarily' happen.[65]  This according to Craig limits God free action, placing Him in a temporally contingent position.[66]  The Molinist perspective affirms the conceptualist model where God necessarily has perfect knowledge of what will actually happen, and what possibly could have happened consequent to the divine decree, and simply discerns which truths are necessary and which are counterfactual.[67]  The causal relationship between God's true belief of all true propositions (His free knowledge), and the possible choices available to the free agent (natural knowledge) are severed, removing any need for a temporal necessity.[68] 

     The Middle Knowledge view is also a superior explanation for God's free actions of Providence while preserving the free agency of sentient creatures.[69]  Simple Foreknowledge proponents must grapple with free knowledge prior to His decree because the choice of certain circumstances could 'foreordain' men to choose evil.[70]  Without knowing logically prior to His decree what free agents 'would do' (His natural knowledge) God would only have providential freedom to act posterior to His decree to foreordain what He knows 'will be' (His free knowledge), thus emptying any meaning of the concept of foreordination.[71]

     Craig then addresses an Open Theism philosophical argument that God is not able to know future contingencies.  This 'truth maker' argument states that a proposition is not true unless it is actualized in reality, and by deduction, counterfactuals cannot be true.[72]  Craig responds that factually true propositions can be found that do not have 'reality' as a property because they are negations ─ such as "dinosaurs are extinct," and therefore the 'truth maker' argument fails.[73]

Responses to the Middle Knowledge View

Boyd argues the Middle Knowledge view never explains how counterfactuals can be true propositions if neither God nor creaturely agents ever willed them to be so.[74]  Hunt contends Middle Knowledge never addresses the problem of evil, given that the majority of people will reside in hell; God was somehow rendered unable to solve this problem.[75]  Hunt questions the philosophical basis of counterfactuals because both the antecedent presumes what is not true, but then relies on the consequent to follow with what is true.[76]  Helm clarifies that God's knowledge of counterfactuals only applies to the actual world, logically subsequent to His decree, and that Middle Knowledge does not resolve the difficulty of fatalism by simply arguing that God chose the world where these counterfactual events did not happen.[77]

Augustinian-Calvinist View

     The Augustinian-Calvinist view contends divine foreknowledge is logically coherent with the compatibilist view of human freedom, and if accepted, removes the need to resolve any conflict between God's foreknowledge and deterministic free agency.[78]  God's knowledge is the cause of all things; what He causes, He permits because there is no distinction between His knowledge and His Will.[79]  God's foreknowledge is simply His knowledge of what He has decreed before it takes effect ─this is coextensive with divine foreordination, but differs in meaning.[80]

Augustinian-Calvinist View Supporting Arguments

     Scripture that pictures God as surprised, forgetful, or reacting to human choices must necessarily be interpreted metaphorically.[81]  Scripture teaches God ordains everything that happens, even actions of omission or evil by humans, yet those sinners are still accountable for all decisions made under their control.[82]  The responsibility of compatibilistic free agents resides between two fixed points ─ under God who judges thoughts and intentions, and human agents who judge actions.[83]  Since the characteristics of God's relationship to man is unparalleled in human experience, we cannot fully understand it or deny the logical coherence between God's foreordination of events and human accountability for their actions.[84]

Foreknowledge, Freedom and Divine Grace

     Helm argues divine Grace is consistent with compatiblism and that human actions are free 'in a sense' that is consistent with determinism.[85]  The incompatibilist view holds God's grace is causally necessary, but not sufficient for saving faith; a choice must be made by the incompatibilist free agent to accept that grace.[86]  The compatibilistic view is that grace is irresistible and alone causally sufficient.[87]  Incompatibilism requires the free agent to act outside of their sin nature and ranks man's inalienable freedoms equal to God's power to save.[88]  The Augustinian-Calvinist view posits that "...with such freedom, God's saving grace is always resistible, and so saving grace can never ensure its intended effect."[89]

     The maximal definition of God's omniscience is congruent with the compatibilist view because 'indeterministic free actions" would necessarily be outside the realm of God's knowledge to actualize or govern.[90]  Helm responds to the argument from Middle Knowledge that these counterfactual propositions are merely conditional selections, which God has not chosen to actualize.[91] 

God's Righteousness and Knowledge of Evil

     As God acts in the highest and holiest purpose, He permits actions that are evil by removing His controlling influence and allowing human nature to rule.[92]  Incompatibilist objections are not persuasive on this issue because they cannot explain why humans always will choose evil in a wholly good world created by God.  "Accounting for the arrival if evil in a world created good by God...the Augustinian says that the removal of God's hand led to the encroachment of evil ─ to the operation of a causal force arising from a deficiency ─ that God is not and could not Himself be the author ."[93]  "So a God who is essentially strongly omniscient positively governs all acts that occur except those which are evil, and He negatively governs evil acts by knowingly and willingly permitting them."[94]  

     The incompatibilist model cannot be true since God foreknows our future actions in the past, they must necessarily happen in order to by true in God's Mind.[95]  God foreknows 'soft' or 'temporally' true events in the future, and since His knowledge is infallible, they are 'hard" facts to Him, negating the incompatibilist free will argument.[96]

Responses to the Augustinian-Calvinist View

     Affirming libertarian free agency, Boyd argues the Augustinian-Calvinist view has "...God Himself [choosing] to save some and not others..." and that this contradicts scriptural teaching that "God's love is universal and impartial..."[97] and that "if it was only up to God to choose who would be saved, we have every reason to believe He would choose everyone."[98]  Hunt argues that compatiblism is incoherent with moral responsibility, and that the Augustinian-Calvinist view takes the extreme position that man 'cannot' want to do God's will in any situation in his fallen state ever.[99]  

     Finally, Craig argues that the Augustinian-Calvinist attempt to reconcile compatiblism with God's foreknowledge is misguided.[100]  God offers an escape for temptation (I Cor 10:13) which presupposes free agency to pray for grace.[101]  Without Middle Knowledge, "...how can God know what creatures would do were He to withdraw His steadying hand?"[102]  Craig concludes the Augustinian-Calvinist view must presume upon some form of secondary causes to explain free agent decisions, which is logically inconsistent with compatiblism and divine providence.[103]



[1] James K. Beilby and Paul R. Eddy, eds. Divine Foreknowledge: Four Views (Carlisle, Cumbria, UK: Paternoster Press, 2002)
[2] Based on text only, without counting headers and footnotes.
[3] Gregory A. Boyd, "The Open Theism View," Divine Foreknowledge: Four Views, eds. James K. Beilby and Paul R. Eddy (Carlisle, Cumbria, UK: Paternoster Press, 2002), p. 17
[4] Paul Helm, "The Augustinian-Calvinist View," Divine Foreknowledge: Four Views, eds. James K. Beilby and Paul R. Eddy (Carlisle, Cumbria, UK: Paternoster Press, 2002), pp.162-163 synthesized and summarized.
[5] David Hunt, "The Simple Foreknowledge View,"  Divine Foreknowledge: Four Views, eds. James K. Beilby and Paul R. Eddy (Carlisle, Cumbria, UK: Paternoster Press, 2002), p. 101
[6] William Craig, "The Middle-Knowledge View,"  Divine Foreknowledge: Four Views, eds. James K. Beilby and Paul R. Eddy (Carlisle, Cumbria, UK: Paternoster Press, 2002), p. 143 synthesized and summarized
[7] Beilby, p. 9
[8] Boyd, "The Open Theism View," pp. 13-14 synthesized and summarized
[9] Ibid., p. 14
[10] Isaiah 46:10a, Holman Christian Standard Bible (HCSB) (Nashville: Holman Bible Publishers, 2009)
[11] Boyd "The Open Theism View," p. 17
[12] Ibid., p. 19
[13] Boyd "The Open Theism View," p. 23, see also footnote 12
[14] Ibid., pp. 24-26 Boyd cites Isaiah 5:4-5, and Jeremiah 3:6-7, 3:19:20, 7:31, 19:5 and 32:35 where God expresses surprise, regret in Genesis 6:6 for man's descent into depravity, and frustration in I Samuel 13:13 when His plans to bless Saul's family for future generations go unfulfilled.
[15] Ibid., pp. 26-26
[16] Ibid., pp. 28-29 synthesized and summarized
[17] Ibid., p. 29
[18] Ibid., pp. 30-31 Boyd references Exodus 13:17, Jeremiah 26:3, Ezekiel 12:3, 1 Chronicles 2:15, and Matthew 26:39 as instances where God thinks of the future in terms of possibilities and not settled
[19] Ibid., p. 31
[20] Ibid., pp. 34-35, synthesized and summarized
[21] Hunt "A Simple Foreknowledge Response," p. 49
[22] Ibid., p. 50, 53
[23] Ibid., p. 53
[24] Craig "A Middle-Knowledge Response," p. 55
[25] Ibid., p. 53
[26] Ibid., p. 57 [for any proposition P, P is either true or false]
[27] Helm "An Augustinian-Calvinist Response," pp. 61-63
[28] Ibid., p. 63
[29] Helm "An Augustinian-Calvinist Response," p. 64
[30] Hunt "The Simple Foreknowledge View," pp. 65-66, synthesized and summarized
[31] Ibid., p. 67
[32] Ibid., p. 68
[33] Ibid., p. 68, summarized
[34] Ibid., p. 69
[35] Ibid., pp. 72-78, synthesized and summarized
[36] Hunt "The Simple Foreknowledge View," pp. 78-79  summarized
[37] Ibid., p. 79
[38] Ibid., pp. 82-86  summarized
[39] Ibid., pp. 88-89 (Hunt cites Augustine, The Predestination of the Saints, 10.19)
[40] Ibid., p. 90
[41] Ibid., p. 91
[42] Ibid., pp. 91-96
[43] Hunt "The Simple Foreknowledge View," p. 96
[44] Ibid., p. 100
[45] Ibid., p. 101
[46] Boyd "An Open-Theism Response," p. 107
[47] Ibid., p. 108
[48] Craig "A Middle-Knowledge Response," p. 108
[49] Ibid., p. 108             
[50] Craig "A Middle-Knowledge Response," p. 110
[51] Ibid., p. 113
[52] Helm "An Augustinian-Calvinist Response," pp. 115-116
[53] Ibid., p. 117
[54] Ibid., p. 116
[55] Craig, "The Middle-Knowledge View," p. 119-121 synthesized and summarized
[56] Craig, "The Middle-Knowledge View," p. 120
[57] Ibid., p. 121
[58] Ibid., p. 121
[59] Ibid., p. 121
[60] Ibid., p. 122
[61] Ibid., p. 122
[62] Ibid., pp. 123-124  (Jeremiah 38:17-18 is cited)
[63] Craig, "The Middle-Knowledge View," p. 124  (Isaiah 38:1-5, Amos 7:1-6, and Jonah 3:1-10 are cited)
[64] Ibid., p. 123  (John 18:36 paraphrased)
[65] Ibid., p. 126
[66] Ibid., p. 127
[67] Ibid., pp. 131-133  summarized
[68] Ibid., p. 131
[69] Ibid., p. 134
[70] Ibid., p. 135
[71] Craig, "The Middle-Knowledge View," p. 136
[72] Ibid., p. 139
[73] Ibid., pp. 139-142  synthesized and summarized
[74] Boyd, "An Open-Theism Response," p. 145
[75] Hunt, "A Simple-Foreknowledge Response," pp. 151-153  summarized
[76] Ibid., p. 153
[77] Helm, "An Augustinian-Calvinist Response," pp. 156-158  summarized
[78] Helm, "The Augustinian-Calvinist View," p. 162
[79] Ibid., p. 163
[80] Ibid.
[81] Ibid., p. 165
[82] Ibid.
[83] Ibid., p. 166
[84] Ibid., p. 169
[85] Helm, "The Augustinian-Calvinist View," p. 169
[86] Ibid., pp. 169-170  synthesized and summarized
[87] Ibid., p. 170
[88] Ibid., pp. 170-171
[89] Ibid., p. 170
[90] Ibid., p. 175
[91] Ibid.
[92] Ibid., p. 176
[93] Helm, "The Augustinian-Calvinist View," p. 177
[94] Ibid., pp. 178,179
[95] Ibid., p. 184
[96] Ibid., p. 187
[97] Boyd, "An Open-Theism Response," p. 191  summarized
[98] Ibid., p. 193  [emphasis in original quote]
[99] Hunt, "A Simple-Foreknowledge Response," pp.198-200
[100] Craig, "A Middle-Knowledge Response," p. 203
[101] Ibid., p. 202
[102] Ibid., p. 205
[103] Ibid.

No comments: